Skip to main content

Mohammad Rasekh | 2 Regent J. Glob. Just. & Pub. Pol. 259 (2016)

ABSTRACT

Muslim societies now have embraced, more or less, the ideas and institutions of constitutionalism. It may be said that the rule of law, public consent to the political authority, and basic citizens’ entitlements are among the main constituent elements of constitutionalism. Modern law holds a particular status among those elements. It is, inter alia, state-made and amoral, and functions as a unifying thread in the fabric of constitutionalism, which in turn regulates a nation (i.e., a pluralistic society). Muslims always have insisted that the law should comply with or at least not contradict Sharia. They have in fact conceived modern law as a form, which can and ought to be instantiated with the substance of Sharia. This substance (Sharia) is, however, supposed to be, inter alia, jurist-made and moral. Could such a substance accommodate the public consent orientation and the amoral nature of legal rules that regulate the public life of a pluralistic society, and secure the rights of its members? If the answer is in the negative, what could be the way out?

INTRODUCTION

It goes without saying that over the last one and a half centuries, modern ideas and institutions, and in particular, constitutionalism with its extended ramifications, have found their way into traditional Muslim societies in one way or another.1 The adoption or implementation of constitutional ideas and institutions in those societies, however, has not been an easy task; and the process has not yet reached its culmination point.2 It is difficult to locate a Muslim society that can genuinely assert that it has managed to establish and develop, in a proper sense, constitutional concepts and institutions such as the rule of law, individual liberty and democracy.3

Constitutionalism, as an ideal, which soon will be explored in more detail, has suffered various setbacks in Muslim polities. The setbacks may be classified into two main categories of theoretical and practical, as they may also be divided into political, cultural, social and economic.4 This Article concentrates on one of the theoretical or cultural hindrances to the adoption of constitutionalism by Muslim societies. That is to say, Muslims seem to have misconceived one of the most significant elements (if not the most important element) of modern life, namely the “law.” Hence, they have apparently been unable or unwilling to bring about and benefit from a rather legitimate and functioning political system on the basis of the rule of law.5 In consequence, they have deprived themselves of a healthy economic, social and cultural environment that is usually based, inter alia, on a robust legal system.6

In what follows, first, this Article briefly explains the main pillars of constitutionalism. Second, the characteristic features of the law as a unifying element of these pillars are examined. Third, the concept of Sharia is explored. Fourth, and in the light of the discussions in the previous two sections, the conundrum with which Muslims have been confronted in the age of constitutionalism is illustrated. Finally, this Article concludes by making a few remarks on the likely ways out of the problem.

I. CONSTITUTIONALISM

Constitutionalism is indeed a broad title for various values and institutions that are supposed to limit the powers of the government.7 It may be said, however, that the basic and original value is that of limiting the government to law.8 Even those constraining values that are really complementary to the law, such as the public consent to the political authority and the basic entitlements of the people, ought to be eventually actualized by the law otherwise they merely remain at a rhetorical level with no practical impact.9 It should be added that the limitation imposed by law defines both the range of powers and legitimacy of the government.10 On the other hand, putting aside the possibility that governments can limit themselves willingly, the idea of constitution has been put forward in order to entrench the said constraints in such a way that power-holders may not readily remove them.11

Accordingly, the first pillar of constitutionalism is the idea and institution of the rule of law.12 The core idea of the rule of law refers to the substitution of the rule of man by the rule of law.13 That is to say, the rule of law has been constantly believed to be, and is indeed, among other things, the best way of countering the problem of the arbitrary rule of a man or a group of men over other members of a society, due to which most of the misfortunes of social life arise.14

The second pillar of constitutionalism is the system of separation of powers.15 The necessities of an efficient management of public affairs, and also the idea of the imposition of limits on this management have led to a division of labor among the holders of public powers—a mechanism that was later called the separation of powers of the government (i.e., the separation of the legislature, the judiciary and the executive).16 Also, in order for the division of powers and responsibilities not to undermine the rule of law, it is required to be a balanced separation.17 The government must be balanced in the sense that none of the three powers should hold so much power and discretion that outweighs the other two. Hence, any imbalance means one branch is able to interfere with and exert influence on another branch’s proper functioning, thus leading to an arbitrary method of governance.18

The third pillar of constitutionalism, public consent, took shape when endeavors were made to find an answer to the question raised against the wide range of powers and responsibilities held by the government at the early modern era.19 In other words, public governance reached a point in its history where the divine and natural models of, and justifications for, an extended and hugely powerful political and administrative authority were no longer considered to be a matter of fact.20 There was indeed a strong demand for some kind of explanation and justification for that authority.21 A theory of public consent was first put forth by certain scholars like Thomas Hobbes,22 and then developed into a social contract framework by others such as Jean-Jacque Rousseau.23 On this basis, only those governing arrangements and powers that had been consented to by the public were legitimate.24


1 See Said Amir Arjomand, Introduction to CONSTITUTIONAL POLITICS IN THE MIDDLE EAST: WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO TURKEY, IRAQ, IRAN, AND AFGHANISTAN 1–3 (Said Amir Arjomand ed., 2008).
2 See id. at 1–10 (tracing the difficulties that the Islamic world has experienced in creating constitutional democracies).
3 See, e.g., id. at 5, 67–70.
4 See Mohammad Hashim Kamali, Constitutionalism in Islamic Countries: A Contemporary Perspective of Islamic Law, in CONSTITUTIONALISM IN ISLAMIC COUNTRIES: BETWEEN UPHEAVAL AND CONTINUITY 19, 19–32 (Rainer Grote & Tilmann J. Roder, eds., 2012); see also Ebrahim Afsah, Contested Universalities of Internal Law: Islam’s Struggle with Modernity, 10 J. HIST. INT’L L. 259, 268–69 (2008).
5 Hossein Esmaeili, The Nature and Development of Law in Islam and the Rule of Law Challenge in the Middle East and the Muslim World, 26 CONN. J. INT’L L. 329, 331 (2010).
6 See WILL KYMLICKA, MULTICULTURAL CITIZENSHIP: A LIBERAL THEORY OF MINORITY RIGHTS 26 (1995) [hereinafter MULTICULTURAL CITIZENSHIP]; Strobe Talbott, Forward to KENNETH, W. DAM, THE LAW-GROWTH NEXUS: THE RULE OF LAW AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT, 14 (2006) (discussing the importance of institutions to creating a strong economy); Stephen Haggard & Lydia Tiede, The Rule of Law and Economic Growth: Where Are We?, 39 WORLD DEV. 673, 681 (2011); Will Kymlicka, The Rise and Fall of Multiculturalism? New Debates on Inclusion and Accommodation in Diverse Societies, 61 INT’L SOC. SCI. J. 97, 106–08 (2010) (explaining how instability causes fear and suppression of minorities, whereas when nations feel secure they are more likely to treat their minorities fairly).
7 See Larry Alexander, Introduction to CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 2–3 (Larry Alexander ed., reprt. 1999) (1998) (discussing the concept of constitutionalism as meta-rules that are composed of agreed upon norms).
8 See N.W. BARBER, THE CONSTITUTIONAL STATE, 78 (2010); CHARLES HOWARD MCILWAIN, CONSTITUTIONALISM: ANCIENT AND MODERN 21 (rev. ed. 1947) (1940); BRIAN TAMANAHA, ON THE RULE OF LAW: HISTORY, POLITICS, THEORY 114 (2004).
9 See M.J.C. VILE, CONSTITUTIONALISM AND THE SEPARATION OF POWERS 1 (1967).
10 See Tom Ginsburg, Constitutionalism: East Asian Antecedents, 88 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 11, 12–13 (2010).
11 Larry Alexander, What are Constitutions, and What Should (and Can) They Do? 28 SOC. PHIL. & POL’Y 1, 3–4 (2011).
12 ALEXANDER, supra note 7, at 4–5.
13 Joseph Raz, The Rule of Law and Its Virtue,  93 L. Q. REV. 195, 196 (1977).
14 See id. at 202–03, 205.
15 VILE, supra note 9, at 1–2.
16 See id.; see also; ERIC BARENDT, AN INTRODUCTION TO CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 14–17 (1998); Torsten Persson et al., Separation of Powers and Accountability, 112 Q. J. ECON. 1163, 1164, 1166–68, 1198–99 (1997).
17 See EOIN CAROLAN, THE NEW SEPARATION OF POWERS: A THEORY FOR THE MODERN STATE 183–84 (2009); JAMES W. CEASER, In Defense of Separation of Powers, in SEPARATION OF POWERS: DOES IT STILL WORK? 168, 179–81, 186 (Robert A. Goldwin & Art Kaufman, eds., 1986); see also D. Brooks Smith, Promoting the Rule of Law and Respecting the Separation of Powers: The Legitimate Role of the American Judiciary Abroad, 7 AVE MARIA L. REV. 1, 18–19 (2008).
18 See VILE, supra note 9, at 2.
19 See Bruce P. Frohnen, A Problem of Power: The Impact of Modern Sovereignty on the Rule of Law in Comparative and Historical Perspective, 20 TRANSNAT’L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 599, 605–06 (2012).
20 MARTIN LOUGHLIN, THE IDEA OF PUBLIC LAW 13–14 (2003).
21 See id. at 13.
22 THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 126, 133, 135 (Oxford Univ. Press 1909) (1651).
23 See Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses, in EVERYMAN’S LIBRARY: PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 14–15 (Ernest Rhys ed., G. D. H. Cole trans., J.M. Dent & Sons Ltd. 1923)(1913) (describing the contract that citizens voluntarily form with society).
24 See JOHN DUNN, Contractualism, in THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THEORY AND OTHER ESSAYS 39, 52, 55–56 (1996); RUSSELL HARDIN, LIBERALISM, CONSTITUTIONALISM, AND DEMOCRACY 141, 146–47, 149 (1999).


† Professor of Public Law and Jurisprudence, Shahid-Beheshti University, Tehran (formerly National University of Iran). The first version of this Article was read during a seminar at the Institute of Ismaili Studies, London, on April 09, 2015. The author would like to express his gratitude to the Institute for giving him the opportunity to share certain ideas with the respectable audience. He deeply appreciates the excellent questions the audience at the seminar put forward, and also would like to thank Dr. Mahnaz Bayat, Faezeh Ameri, Fatemeh Bakhshizadeh and Shirin Boroumand for their valuable comments and assistance in the completion of this Article.